Skip repetitive navigational links
Previous messageNext messagePrevious in topicNext in topicPrevious by same authorNext by same authorPrevious page (September 1999)Back to main PSYCHE-B pageJoin or leave PSYCHE-BReplyPost a new messageSearchProportional fontNon-proportional fontLog in
Date:         Thu, 23 Sep 1999 23:26:24 +1000
Reply-To:     "PSYCHE Discussion Forum (Biological/Psychological emphasis)"
              <[log in to unmask]>
Sender:       "PSYCHE Discussion Forum (Biological/Psychological emphasis)"
              <[log in to unmask]>
From:         Bruce Mangan <[log in to unmask]>
Subject:      Re: Chicken sexing (real scientific inquiry!)
Content-type: text/plain; charset=us-ascii

I've just finished reading the Biederman & Shiffrar (1987) paper on chicken sexing. It contains some indirect evidence for implicit cognition that I'll get to at the end of this note. But the most striking thing about the Biederman paper is that it presents very solid experimental evidence for a consciously mediated process of EXPLICIT cognition. I gather this is just what Minsky asked us for more than a week ago: Who can supply a provable example of explicit cognition. Aha, you claim that you recognize the chicken because of its feet, or its, beak, or its cute little eyes. Well, that's your conscious theory. But most commonsense theories turn out to be wrong-and I suspect that this will often apply to "articulated criteria". I can't let the last sentence above of Minsky's pass without a brief challenge. Maybe he just made a slip of the keyboard. Does Minsky really believe that MOST commonsense theories are wrong? And would he actually have us use this proposition as an evaluative principle in science? Is a theory really more likely to be true if, all else being equal, it *violates* commonsense rather than resonates with it? At least in relation to the humble act of chicken sexing, it looks like we do have, contrary to Minsky's intuition, solid evidence for recognition via articulated feature identification. (1) I find the background of Biederman's experiment fascinating in its own right. The current method for sexing baby chicks (99.4% success rate) was introduced into North America by a group of Japanese chicken sexers invited to the University of British Columbia in 1933. The Japanese technique was to invert the chick's vent (cloaca) and focus on a region of tissue about the size of a pin head. It is still difficult to reliably discriminate male from female this way, in part because there is a good deal of variation among baby chick's genitalia (now called the "bead" in the profession). But by showing their audience numerous physical examples of male and female genitalia augmented by verbal descriptions of the many different kinds of sub-type features (passed laboriously through an interpreter) the Japanese were finally able to transfer their knowledge. Schools of chicken sexing sprang up immediately, and the Japanese technique soon became the standard method for chicken sexing, at least on this continent. In 1984, a human interest story in the San Francisco Chronicle told about the retirement of one Heimer Carlson. He had sexed over 55 million chicks in his career, and was one of the first people to graduate from a chicken sexing school set up immediately after the Japanese excursion to Canada. The experimenters visited Carlson, showed him photos of male and female inverted cloaca taken of difficult genital features to sex, and asked Carlson to circle what he saw as the bead in each picture. I'd estimate that the beads occupy something like 10%-15% of the total area of each photo. To quote Biederman & Shiffar: "Our examination of the [circled photographs of the] beads revealed a simple difference in the contours between males and females. In males, the eminence was convex; in females, flat or concave. This differentiation corresponded to the descriptions offered by some of the sexers who described males as 'round' and females as 'pointy.' When a sketch of shapes of the eminences was drawn ... and showed to Mr. Carlson, he agreed to its diagnosticity." It does not seem from this account that Carlson himself had consciously formulated a round vs. pointy description of baby chick genitalia or some other simple schematic; but Carlson did agree with the remarkably simple diagrams the experimenters devised when they showed them to him. (2) These diagrams then served as the basis of Biederman & Shiffrar's experiment. Their overall procedure and findings were as follows (quoting from the abstract): "Naive subjects were shown 18 pictures of cloacal regions of male and female chicks ... and asked to judge the sex of each chick. The pictures indicated a number of rare and difficult configurations. The subjects were then instructed as to the location of a critical cloacal structure for which a simple contrast in shape (convex vs. concave or flat) could serve as a indicant of sex. When the subjects judged the pictures again ... accuracy increased from slightly above chance to a level comparable to that achieved by a sample of experts. The correlation (over items) between the naive subjects and the experts before instruction was .21; after instruction, .82 .... The rate of learning in these cases could be greatly increased through the use of simple instructions that specified the location of diagnostic contour contrasts." (3) I do not see how anyone could deny that in this case the subject's increased ability to recognize a male or female baby chick was mediated by the antecedent conscious identification of minute features in chicken's sex organs. All it took to do this was a few simple, well chosen diagrams and descriptive phrases. This was enough to shift the behavioral capacity of naive subjects to that of seasoned professionals in the photo identification task. I gather that the instruction phase of the experiment took less than five minutes. Nothing in this means that consciously mediated feature analysis is in general the ONLY cognitive process behind discriminant recognition. It does mean that this "commonsense" theory of recognition is certainly true sometimes, and that recognition via explicit feature identification IS A VERY NATURAL AND POWERFUL COGNITIVE STRATEGY, WELL ADAPTED TO THE OPERATION OF OUR ORGANISM IN GENERAL AND TO THE NEEDS OF CONSCIOUSNESS IN PARTICULAR. Biederman gives a collateral example of American solders learning to distinguish Warsaw Pact from NATO tanks that is also based on a simple feature identification: The back section of all Warsaw tank turrets were completely rounded; NATO tank turrets had linear backs. And of course we all know of a huge number of analogous examples, e.g., the criteria naturalists use in the field to quickly distinguish similar species from one another as opposed to DNA analysis in the lab. In their professional training, chicken sexers are expected to remember many different complex types of sex features. In contrast, the full set of features used in the Biederman and Shiffrar experiment was simplicity itself. Professional training aims to sex-type a host of different rare configurations. It may be that this degree of complex feature analysis is not strictly necessary. (But it would still make sense in the larger social context: The students feel they are getting their money's worth from the chicken sexing schools, and the skill seems more difficult and so perhaps more valuable to the larger world of the poultry industry). These findings also illustrate the plasticity of the feature analysis technique for human cognition. Complex biological systems often accomplish the same end using a variety of means. So, without intending to, the Biederman and Shiffar experiment may also show us it may be possible for either an implicit or an explicit mechanism to accomplish, roughly speaking, the same cognitive end. (4) The indirect evidence for implicit cognition in Biederman's paper derives from the fact that his subjects were able to correctly sex the photos significantly above chance (62% percent) BEFORE they had any instruction in explicit feature identification. Biederman and Shiffar try to explain this by speculating that "the most likely reason for this level of accuracy was that the subjects' not-so-naive hypothesis about what might be diagnostic was partially accurate. For the most part, the presence of a prominent bead -- which is the central singular structure -- was interpreted as being male." There is no report of subjects actually saying anything like this, but by itself this speculation is certainly plausible. However, the paper begins by emphasizing a very different point: "Like many perceptual psychologists, the first author (Irving Biederman) was introduced to this problem by the first figure in E.J Gibson's *Principles of Perceptual Learning and Development* (1969). Professor Gibson had reported a figure from Canfield (1941) that showed the genetic eminences of pullets and cockerel's (Figure 1). Despite a considerable initial effort and occasional attempts distributed over almost two decades at studying this figure [which later served as his experimental stimuli], Biederman was unable to determine what information could be used to distinguish males from females. His experience was not unique: a number of other perceptual and cognitive psychologists that we questioned had also studied that figure and all but one (not verified before the results of this research were discussed with him) admitted to being unable to derive a perceptual basis for the discrimination." Is it likely that undergraduates in a psych pool would be able to *explicitly* recognize a diagnostic feature in these stimuli after a single brief exposure to them, but that many interested graduate students and professional psychologists, after years of careful scrutiny, could NOT explicitly identify the same feature in the stimuli? If the answer is no, then we have good reason to assert that Biederman's study offers experimental evidence for the operation of implicit cognitive mechanisms in chicken sexing for completely naive subjects. In effect, then, this study would seem to straddle the transition from implicit to explicit cognition. It is more difficult to use the Biederman and Shiffrar article to unravel the possible contributions of implicit and/or explicit mechanisms in professional chicken sexers. The professional method of training certainly works, and it also rests on a feature identification assumption. But, again, the features it concerns itself with are far more complex and variable than those identified by Biederman and Shiffrar. Unfortunately there is virtually nothing in their study addressing the phenomenology of chicken sexing beyond the remark that all the professionals interviewed "reported that they could listen to music while working, [and] four of the sexers reported that they could not 'think of anything else' while sexing a chick." On general theoretical grounds, I would expect that an activity like sexing just the most frequent and straightforward types of genitalia would be more likely to implicit cognitive activity, and that this would be represented in consciousness primarily as fringe experience (Mangan, 1991, 1993a, 1993b, 2000). The less frequent and difficult cases would be more likely handled by explicit cognitive mechanisms, represented in consciousness by focal experience of relevant diagnostic feature(s). But professional chicken sexers must work extremely fast (Carlson only spent about half a second looking at each eminence) and must be extremely accurate. There is no way to know when, in the constant flow of chicks, a difficult case will occur. Even if a demanding judgement is requiored only 10% of the time, it would still have to be made every few seconds. So chicken sexing seems to demand a state of constant conscious vigilance. This may help explain why the typical chicken sexer "can't think of anything else." In contrast, workers doing other well learned and highly repetitive tasks such as rolling cigars can at the same time enjoy listening to newspaper articles and novels read to them as they work. This suggests an experiment. Reduce the need for vigilance and other task demands by using a set of chicks from which all the difficult cases were already removed by other sexers. I would expect that a chicken sexer with this less demanding task would begin to report conscious flights of reverie, and otherwise show signs that his or her conscious experience was now able to represent significantly more information about non-chick matters even when their output per minute remained at its previous level. Finally, to come full circle: consider the question Nigel Thomas raised about implicit cognition and chicken sexing that started our discussion early this month: I know I have read somewhere that people who are employed to sort new hatched chicks into males and females typically cannot articulate the criteria on which they do it. That is to say, they do not appear to be conscious of how they are performing the task or of whatever the cues are that they use to distinguish the sexes. They can just tell, as it were. This seems to be an interesting and perhaps historically important example of implicit cognition (I think I heard about this long before implicit cognition was a fashionable research topic). I, too, remember hearing this many years ago. In my memory this is connected with two further points that I doubt I could have manufactured out of the air. This makes it even more unlikely that what Nigel and I heard long ago reflected North American chicken sexing practices. As I recall, the chicken sexers who "just knew" a male chick from a female had been trained using a mass of photographs of male and female chick genitalia. No explicit feature analysis whatsoever. This kind of exposure was by itself supposedly able to produce a reliable chicken sexer. In remarkable contrast to this, Biederman notes that none of the professional chicken sexers he interviewed had even laid eyes on a picture of a chick's genetalia before the experiment. Apparently photos played no part in the Japanese technique as adopted by the Americans. The second thing I recall is that the example of "just knowing" a male from a female baby chick was said at the time to be a favorite example of Australian philosophers. Could it be, then, that there was (or still is) a school of chicken sexing (perhaps in Australia) not based at all on explicit feature analysis, but on purely implicit training and implicit detection? In effect, Biederman's study gives us reasonable grounds to think that implicit mechanisms can do this job to some degree. The question is, how far can this implicit capacity be pushed with training? Bruce Mangan Institute of Cognitive Studies University of California, Berkeley [log in to unmask]


Back to: Top of message | Previous page | Main PSYCHE-B page

LISTSERV.UH.EDU CataList email list search Powered by LISTSERV email list manager