

| |
JOHN LOCKE'S THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE
|
While the change in philosophical thinking is very real, it is
not really out of step with the past. Locke said that we
experience particular things. This is not always clear from his
descriptions of experience. Remember that Aristotle said that
the mind, that part of the soul that thinks, is nothing until it
begins to think. It does not exist as an entity of itself until
it thinks of itself. What Locke said was that the mind is a
blank slate, that it contains no ideas, until it experiences.
Aristotle's concept of experience is
through imagination. Imagination is the image producing
mechanism in the body that produces images of what the senses
detect in the world around us. The mind, in order to image
those thinks it is contemplating or remembering, uses Imagination
to produce those images. Descartes' description follows
Aristotle's very closely particularly when he said that the mind
imagines while at the same time making imagination a part of the
body. When, In An Essay Concerning Human Understanding,
Locke began with the assumption that everything we know we know
only from experience, what he was saying is that ideas are only
derived from experience and the mind can not operate without
ideas.
Locke's theory of knowledge begins with his definition of Ideas
as anything that existed in the mind that could be expressed
through words. Experience, as he described it, is ultimately
derived from only two sources, simple ideas created by our
interaction with sensible qualities in things of the sensible
world, and simple ideas developed out of our observations
concerning the operations of our mind. Locke, although he made a
number remarks concerning them, did not explain how it was that
sensations excite ideas in the mind. He only stated that God
produced in us the capacity for doing so.
What Locke called "qualities" are those characteristics of
objects which cause ideas in our mind through sensation. There
are two kinds of qualities in objects. Primary, or real,
qualities are those that always exist in an object. These would
include solidity, extension, figure, number, and motion or rest.
They are always connected with the object whether we sense them
or not. Secondary, or imputed, qualities consist of combinations
of several primary qualities where we do not recognize these
primary qualities distinctly. When we sense particular things,
for example, we sense along with them a quality of unity and
though the primary qualities are there what we perceive is not
them but the object itself. For example, we may sense a certain
texture, a particular form, a specific animal odor. These would
be simple ideas formed by primary qualities. We may also sense a
leather chair, which would be a simple idea produced by secondary
qualities. But if we were to analyze the idea of a leather chair
into its constituent qualities of feel, form, and sense, that
would constitute a set of complex ideas developed by the mind out
of the simple ideas formed through sense. Perception is the
immediate occasion of an idea previously formed by judgment that
has been activated by sensation. Thus, when someone recognizes
the full extent of an object known from past judgments at the
moment of the sensation of the object.
This concept of particular objects forming simple ideas and of
perceptions being always of actual things bothered many who
otherwise followed Locke's train of thought. But we must
remember that immediate perception is more than just a
philosophical notion. A prehistoric man facing a charging saber-toothed tiger, or a modern man facing a careening out of control
automobile both have the same problem. They must react
immediately. There is no time for judgment. The mind is simply
too slow. If man did not have the capability of immediate action
without mental consideration, he would have been extinct long
ago. Descartes made that ability a basic part of his description
of the relation between sense and action, saying that animal
spirits can directly initiate action. This is one of the
shortcomings of the more idealistic empiricism of both Berkeley
and Hume as we will presently discover. As Locke explained
perception, it is an immediate connection between sensation and a
pre-established judgment. The judgment must already exist,
having been developed through previous experience. Then and only
then can the mind arrive at the perception. This makes sense if
you consider that the first time you experience something it
takes a period of time before you realize exactly what it is you
have perceived. It has an advantage over Descartes in that by
including in the description elements formed from previous
experience, it illustrates its dependence on both experience and
learning.
The beginning of our treatment of things in our sensual world,
Aristotle said, is through naming them. Locke has taken the
stand that the things we are dealing with mentally are not the
things that we sense, but the ideas that are formed in our minds
by what we sense.
The use of words then being to stand as outward marks of our
internal ideas, and those ideas being taken from particular
things, if every particular idea that we take in should have
a distinct name, names must be endless. To prevent this,
the mind makes the particular ideas received from particular
objects to become general; which is done by considering them
as they are in the mind such appearances--separate from all
other existences, and circumstances of real existence, as
time, place, or any other concomitant ideas. This is called
abstraction, whereby ideas taken from particular beings
become general representatives of all of the same kind; and
their names general names, applicable to whatever exists
conformable to such abstract ideas.
|
One of the major criticisms of Locke's theory of knowledge deals
with his statement that we can know not only space but also
immense and perhaps infinite space through experience. But
consider along this line that part of our experience includes the
simple ideas of individual objects, each as a unity of simple
sensations which are of themselves only confusedly sensed. The
analysis of these simple ideas will result in complex ideas of
the constituent elements. In other words the simple ideas of
animal odor, specific form, and feel or texture are determined of
their own accord. But the feel, odor, and forms of leather
chairs are complex ideas developed through reflection and
abstraction from the simple idea of a leather chair. Thus
distance or length is a part of the unity of a simple object,
when reflected on, it becomes a component of a class of objects,
such as leather chairs. Once extracted from the complex idea of
leather chairs, it becomes something of its own. Though it is no
longer dependent on experience, it could not have been developed
outside of experience. But there is nothing unusual about
expanding the limit of a complex idea created out of simple ideas
in the mind to such ideas as immensity or infinity. It is just
that such ideas since they were formed in the mind and not
developed directly from experience are abstract.
However, in order for our minds to operate on even simple ideas
it must first name them. At the same time he said that names are
determined by public agreement. This is necessary because he
assumed the only purpose of language to be communication. Public
agreement, of course, entails a necessarily public language.
However, since words are symbols for ideas and ideas are not
communicable, they exist only in the mind, they are symbols for
what is necessarily private. It would seem, however, that if
language is necessarily public then it must exist first before we
can name simple ideas and subsequently before we develop any
complex ideas. To make matters worse, since we deal almost
exclusively in abstract ideas, the exact nature of anyone's
internal ideas can never be determined. As a result, a complex
language must exist before knowledge of the external world can
even be approximated. This is a fascinating problem, but one
which neither Locke, nor any subsequent philosopher has attempted
to solve.
|
|